Núm. 53 (2017): Julio-diciembre
Artículos

La composicionalidad del lenguaje revisitada

Mariela Destefano
Universidad de Buenos Aires Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Tecnológicas
Biografía

Publicado 2017-07-01

Cómo citar

Destefano, M. (2017). La composicionalidad del lenguaje revisitada. Tópicos, Revista De Filosofía, (53), 51. https://doi.org/10.21555/top.v0i53.844

Descargas

Los datos de descargas todavía no están disponibles.

Altmetrics

Citas

Resumen

En este trabajo intentaré mostrar que el lenguaje es composicional desde la perspectiva del programa minimalista. Desde este enfoque adoptaré la noción de “lengua-I”. Específicamente, intentaré sostener que, si el minimalismo es correcto, el producto de la lengua-I es composicional en virtud de restricciones generales de arquitectura cognitiva y restricciones intrínsecas al mecanismo computacional de la lengua-I. Mi argumento puede entenderse como una inferencia a la mejor explicación. La mejor explicación de que la lengua-I, en tanto sistema de expresiones que sirven de instrucciones semánticas para la interfaz conceptual-intencional, genere computacionalmente esas instrucciones y responda óptimamente a las condiciones de interfaz es, en parte, atribuyéndole composicionalidad semántica a dichas expresiones. 

Citas

  1. Aizawa, K. (2003). The Systematicity Arguments. New York: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  2. Belletti, A. (2004). Structures and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  3. Berwick, R., C. y Chomsky, N. (2011). The Biolinguistic Program: The Current State of its Development. En A. M. Di Sciullo y C. Boeckx (eds.) The Biolinguistic Enterprise: New Perspectives on the Evolution and Nature of the Human Language Faculty. (19-41). Oxford: Oxford
  4. University Press.
  5. Bezuidenhoout, A. y Reimer, M. (2004). Descriptions and Beyond: An Interdisciplinary Collection of Essays on Definite and Indefinite Descriptions and Other Related Phenomena. Oxford: OUP.
  6. Boeckx, C. (2012). The I-Language Mosaic. En C. Boeckx y M.C Horno- Chéliz (eds.) Language from a Biological Point of View. Current Issues on Biolinguistics. (23-51). Cambridge: Cambirdge Scholars Publishing.
  7. ____ (2011) The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism. Oxford: OUP.
  8. ____ (2009). The Nature of Merge: Consequences for Language, Mind, and Biology. En M. Piattelli-Palmarini, J. Uriagereka, y P. Salaburu (eds.) Of Minds and Language. (44-57). Oxford: OUP.
  9. Boeckx y M.C Horno-Chéliz (eds.) (2012). Language from a Biological Point of View. Current Issues on Biolinguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
  10. Calvo, P. y Simons, J. (2009). Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology. New York: Routledge.
  11. Camp, E. (2004). The Generality Constraint: Nonsense and Categorial Restrictions. En Philosophical Quarterly, 54, 209-231.
  12. ____ (2007). Thinking with Maps. En Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 147- 182.
  13. Chomsky, N. (2014). Minimal Recursion: Exploring the Prospects. En T. Roeper y M. Speas (eds.) Recursion: Complexity in Cognition. (1-15). Amherst, MA: Springer.
  14. ____ (2010). Some Simple Evo-devo Theses: How True might they be for Language? En R. K. Larson, V. Déprez y H. Yamakido (eds.) The Evolution of Human Language: Biolinguistic Perspectives. (45-62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  15. ____ (2008). On Phrases. En: R. Freidin, C. Otero y M. L. Zubizarreta (eds). Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory. (133-162). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  16. ____ (2007). Approaching UG form below. En Interfaces + Recursion = Language? Chomsky`s Minimalism and the View from Syntax-Semantics. Mouton: de Guyer.
  17. ____ (2006). Biolinguistic Exploration: design, development, evolution. En International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 15 (1).
  18. ____ (2005a). Three Factors in Linguistic Design. En Linguistic Inquiry, 36, 1-22.
  19. ____ (2005b). On Phases. Manuscrito.
  20. ____ (2004a). Beyond Explanatory Adequacy. En A. Belletti (ed.) Structures and beyond.(104-131). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  21. ____ (2004b). The generative enterprise revisited. Berlín: Mouton de Gruyter.
  22. ____ (2003). La arquitectura del lenguaje. Barcelona: Kairo.
  23. ____ (2002). New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind. Cambridge: CUP.
  24. ____ (1995a). El programa minimalista. Madrid: Alianza.
  25. ____ (1995b). Language and Nature. En Mind, 104, 1-61.
  26. Clapp, L. (2010). Is even Thought Compositional? En Philosophical Studies, 10.1007/s11098-010-9649-2, Online First.
  27. Collins, J. (2011). Chomsky. En B. Lee (ed.) Philosophy of Language. Key Thinkers. (41-59). Londres, Nueva York: Continuum.
  28. ____ (2009). Naturalism in the Philosophy of Language; or Why there is no Such Thing as Language. En New Waves in Philosophy: Philosophy of Language. (41-69). Londres: Palgrave-Macmillan.
  29. Di Sciullo, A. y Boeckx, C. (2011). The Biolinguistic Enterprise: New Perspectives on the Evolution and Nature of the Human Language Faculty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  30. Eguren, L. (2014). La gramática universal en el programa minimalista. En Revista de Lingüística Teórica y Aplicada, 52 (1), 35-58.
  31. Elugardo, R. (2005). Fodor’s Inexplicitness Argument. En E. Machery, G. Schurz, y M. Werning (eds.) The Compositionality of Concepts and Meanings. Volume I: Foundational Issues. (59-86). Germany: Ontos Verlag.
  32. Evans, G. (1982). Varieties of Reference. Oxford: OUP.
  33. Fodor, J. (2008). LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford: OUP.
  34. ____ (2001). Language, Thought and Compositionality. En Mind and Language, 16, 1–15.
  35. ____ (1998). Conceptos. Donde la ciencia cognitiva se equivocó. Barcelona: Gedisa.
  36. ____ (1975). El lenguaje del pensamiento. Madrid: Alianza.
  37. Fodor, J. y Pylyshyn, Z.W. (1995). Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis. En C. McDonald y G. McDonald (eds.) Connectionism. (90-163). MA: Blackwell.
  38. Fodor, J. y Lepore, E. (2002). The Compositionality Papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  39. Freidin, R., Otero, C. y Zubizarreta, M. L. (2008). Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  40. Fromkin, V., Rodman, R. y Hyams, N. (2003). An Introduction to Language. MASS: Thomson.
  41. Hauser, M.D., Chomsky, N., y Ficht, W. T. (2002). The Faculty of Language: What Is it, who Has it, and how did it Evolve? En Science, 298, 1569-1579.
  42. Hale, B. y Wright, C. (1997). A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Blackwell.
  43. Hinzen, W. (2014). Recursion and Truth. En T. Roeper y M. Speas (eds.) Recursion: Complexity in Cognition. (113-137). Amherst, MA:
  44. ____ (2009). Hierarchy, Merge, and Truth*. En M. Piattelli-Palmarini, J. Uriagereka, y P. Salaburu (eds.) Of Minds and Language. (123-141). Oxford: OUP.
  45. Hodges, W. (1998). Compositionality is not the Problem. En Logic and Logical Philosophy, 6, 7-33.
  46. Hornstein, N., Nunes, J. y J.K. Grohmann. (2004). Undestanding Minimalism: An Introduction to Minimalist Syntax. Cambridge: CUP.
  47. Hulst, Van Der. (2010). Recursion and Human Language. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
  48. Jackendoff, R. (2003). Foundations of Language. Oxford: OUP.
  49. Larson, R. K., Déprez, V. y Yamakido, H. (2010). The evolution of human language: Biolinguistic perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  50. Lee, B. (2011). Philosophy of Language. Key Thinkers. Londres, Nueva York: Continuum.
  51. Lievers, M. (2005). The Structure of Thought. En E. Machery, G. Schurz, y M. Werning (eds.) The Compositionality of Concepts and Meanings. Volume I: Foundational Issues. (7-21). Germany: Ontos Verlag.
  52. Ludlow, P. (2014). Recursion, Legibility, Use. En T. Roeper y M. Speas (eds.) Recursion: Complexity in Cognition. (89-112). Amherst, MA: Springer.
  53. Machery, G. Schurz, y M. Werning, M. (2005). The Compositionality of Concepts and Meanings. Volume I: Foundational Issues. Germany: Ontos Verlag.
  54. Machery, G. Schurz, y M. Werning, M. (2005). Preface. En E. Machery, G. Schurz, y M. Werning (eds.) The Compositionality of Concepts and Meanings. Volume I: Foundational Issues. (7-21). Germany: Ontos Verlag.
  55. Maran , A. (1995). The Minimalist Program. En G. Webelhuth (ed.) Government and Binding Theory and the Minimalist Program. (352-382). Cambridge, Massachussetts: Blackwell.
  56. Mcdonald, C. y Mcdonald, G. (1995). Connectionism. MA: Blackwell.
  57. Neale, S. (2004). This, That, and the Other. En A. Bezuidenhoout y M. Reimer (eds.) Descriptions and Beyond: An Interdisciplinary Collection of Essays on De nite and Inde nite Descriptions and Other Related Phenomena. (68-182). Oxford: OUP.
  58. Peacocke, C. (1992). A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  59. Piattelli-Palmarini, M., Uriagereka, J. y Salaburu, P. (2009). Of Minds and Language. Oxford: OUP.
  60. Piccinini, G. (2007). Computing Mechanisms. En Philosophy of Science, 74 (4).
  61. Pietroski, P. (2008). Minimalist Meaning, Internalist Interpretation. En Biolinguisticas, 2 (4), 317-341.
  62. RecanatI, F. (2004). Literal Meaning. Cambridge: CUP.
  63. Reuland, E. (2011). Syntax and Interpretation Systems: How is their Labour Divided? En C. Boeckx (ed). The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism. Oxford: OUP.
  64. Roeper, T. y Speas, M. (2014). Recursion: Complexity in Cognition. Amherst, MA: Springer.
  65. Schneider, S. (2009). The Language of Thought. En P. Calvo y J. Simons (eds.) Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology. (280-295). New York: Routledge.
  66. Speas, M. (2014). Recursion: Complexity in Cognition. En T. Roeper y M. Speas (eds.) Recursion: Complexity in Cognition. (x-xxi). Amherst, MA: Springer.
  67. Travis, CH. (1997). Pragmatics. En B. Hale y C. Wright (eds.) A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. (87-107). Blackwell.
  68. Vicente, A. y Martínez-Manrique, F. (2008). Thought, Language, and the Argument from Explicitness. En Metaphilosophy, 39 (3), 381-401.
  69. Webelhuth, G. (1995). Government and Binding Theory and the Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Massachusse s: Blackwell.