Número 42 - 2012
Articles

Avicennan troubles: The mysteries of the heptagonal house and of the phoenix

Thérèse-Anne Druart
Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile

Published 2013-11-28

How to Cite

Druart, T.-A. (2013). Avicennan troubles: The mysteries of the heptagonal house and of the phoenix. Tópicos, Revista De Filosofía, 42(1), 51–73. https://doi.org/10.21555/top.v42i1.61

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

Altmetrics

Citas

Abstract

In the Metaphysics of the Shifâ Avicenna distinguishes three ways in which universals are said. The second sense is puzzling since Avicenna explains that universals are said of what it is permissible to say of many, even if it is not a condition that these many should exist in actuality, and he illustrates this kind of universals with the “heptagonal house”. In its nature this universal can be said of many, but it does not follow necessarily that these many must exist -not even one of them. This second case deals with a less common type of universal, since such universals may have either only one instantiation or even none at all. The example of the heptagonal house is not traditional, as Greek sources, such as Porphyry and Simplicius, use the phoenix instead. In this paper Thérèse-Anne Druart explores in depth the use of this particular illustration, namely, the “heptagonal house”.

References

  1. Ibn Sînâ (1960), Al-Shifâ’, Al-Ilâhiyyât (1) (La métaphysique), ed. G.C. Anawati & Sa’id Zayed, with an intro. by Ibrahim Madkour, Cairo, Organisation Générale des Imprimeries Gouvernementales.
  2. Ibn Sînâ (1970), Al-Shifâ’, La logique, III De l’interprétation (alibara), ed. M. el-Khodeiri, Preface by I. Madkour, Cairo, Dar el-Katib al-‘arabi.
  3. Ibn Sînâ (1983), Al-Ishârât wa-t-tanbîhât, part I, ed. S. Donyâ, Cairo, Dâr al-ma’âref.
  4. Ibn Sînâ (1985), Najât, ed. D. Pazhuh, Tehran, Dâneshgah Tehran.
  5. Avicenna (2009), The Physics of the Healing, Books III & IV, A parallel English-Arabic text transl. introduced, and annotated by J. McGin nis (Islamic Translation Series), Provo, Utah, Brigham Young University Press.
  6. Avicenna (2003), Metafisica, con testo arabo e latino, ed. O. Lizzini & P. Porro (Il pensiero occidentale), Milan, Bompiani.
  7. Avicenna (2005), The Metaphysics of The Healing, A parallel English-Arabic text transl., introduced, and annotated by M. E. Marmura (Islamic Translation Series),Provo, Utah, Brigham Young University Press.
  8. Avicenna (1985), “Avicenna’s ‘Letter on the Disappearance of the Vain Intelligible Forms after Death,”ed. J. Michot, in Bulletin de Philosophie médiévale, 27, 94-103.
  9. Avicenna Latinus (1980), Liber de philosophia prima sive scientia divina, V-X, ed. S. Van Riet, with an intro. by G. Verbeke, Louvain, Peeters & Leiden, E.J. Brill.
  10. Avicenne (1986), Le livre de science, I: Logique, Métaphysique, transl. M. Achena & H. Massé (Traductions de textes persans), Paris, Les Belles Lettres/UNESCO [reprint of 1955].
  11. Avicenne (1987), “ ‘L’épître sur la disparition des formes intelligibles vaines après la mort’ d’Avicenne,” ed. and transl. J. Michot in Bulletin de Philosophie médiévale, 29, 152-67.
  12. Avicenne (2006), Réfutation de l’astrologie, ed., translation, intro., and notes Y. Michot (Sagesses musulmanes, 5), Beirut, Albouraq.
  13. Avicenne (1978), La métaphysique du Shifâ’, Livres I à V, transl. with intro. and notes by G. C. Anawati (Etudes musulmanes XXI), Paris, Vrin.
  14. [al-Fârâbî] (1960), Alfarabi’s Commentary on Aristotle’s Peri Hermeneias (De interpretatione), Arabic ed. with an intro W. Kutsch & S. Marrow, Beirut, Imprimerie Catholique.
  15. Porphyry (1992), On Aristotle’s Categories, transl. S. K. Strange, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press.
  16. Porphyre (2008), Commentaire aux Catégories d’Aristote, critical ed., French transl., and notes R. Bodéüs (Bibliothèque des textes philosophiques), Paris, Vrin. Alon I (2002), Al-Fârâbî’s
  17. Philosophical Lexicon, vol. I, Arabic Text, Vol. II, English Translation, no city, E.J.W. Gibb Memorial Trust.
  18. Bäck, A. (1987), “Avicenna on Existence,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 25, 351-67.
  19. Bäck, A. (1992), “Avicenna’s Conception of the Modalities,” Vivarium, 30, 217-55. Bertolacci, A. (2006), The Reception of Aristotle’s Metaphysics in Avicenna’s Kitâb al-Shifâ’: A Milestone of Western Metaphysical Thought (Islamic Philosophy, Theology and Science, 63), Leiden, Brill.
  20. Black, D.L. (1999), “Mental Existence in Thomas Aquinas and Avicenna,” Mediaeval Studies, 61, 45-79.
  21. Black, D.L. (1997), “Avicenna on the Ontological and Epistemic Status of Fictional Beings,” Documenti e Studi, 8, 425-53.
  22. Black, D. L. (1993), “Estimation (Wahm) in Avicenna: The Logical and Psychological Dimensions,” Dialogue, 32, 227-32.
  23. Bonmariage, E. C. (2007), Le réel et les réalités. Mullâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî et la structure de la réalité (Etudes musulmanes 41), Paris, Vrin.
  24. D’Ancona, C. (2008) entry “Aristotle and Aristotelianism,” in Encyclopaedia Islamica, 3r ed., fasc. 1, 153-69.
  25. de Libera, A. (1996), La querelle des universaux. De Platon à la fin du Moyen Âge, Paris, Seuil.
  26. de Libera, A. (1999), L’art des généralités. Théories de l’abstraction (Philosophie), Paris, Aubier.
  27. Gutas, D. (1988), Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition: Introduction to Reading Avicenna’s Philosophical Works (Islamic Philosophy and Theology, 4), Leiden, Brill.
  28. Hogendijk, J.P. (1984), “Greek and Arabic Constructions of the Regular Heptagon,” Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 30, 197-330.
  29. Inati, S.C. (1984), “An Examination of Ibn Sînâ’s Theodicy: Dissolving the problem of Evil,” The New Scholasticism, 58, 170-86.
  30. Inati, S.C. (2000), The Problem of Evil: Ibn Sînâ’s Theodicy, Binghamton, N.Y., Global Publications.
  31. Janssens, J. (2006), “Avicenne,” in Le vocabulaire des philosophes, Supplements I, vol. V, ed. P. Magnard, Paris, Ellipses, 13-64.
  32. Katayama, E.G. (1999), Aristotle on Artifacts: A Metaphysical Puzzle (SUNY Series in Ancient Greek Philosophy), Albany, State University of New York Press.
  33. Kennedy-Day, K. (2003), Books of Definition in Islamic Philosophy: The Limits of Words, London, Routledge Curzon.
  34. Marmura, M.E. (1962), “Some Aspects of Avicenna’s Theory of God’s Knowledge of Particulars,” in his Probing in Islamic Philosophy: Studies in the Philosophies of Ibn Sina, al-Ghazali and other Major Muslim Thinkers, Binghamton, N.Y., Global Academic Publishing, 2005, 71- 95 (originally published in 1962).
  35. Marmura, M.E. (1979), “Avicenna’s Chapter on the Universals in the Isagogue of his Shifâ’,” in his Probing in Islamic Philosophy: Studies in the Philosophies of Ibn Sina, al-Ghazali and other Major Muslim Thinkers, Binghamton, N.Y., Global Academic Publishing, 2005, pp. 33- 59 (originally 1979).
  36. Marmura, M.E., (1992), “Quiddity and Universality in Avicenna,” in his Probing in Islamic Philosophy: Studies in the Philosophies of Ibn Sina, al-Ghazali and other Major Muslim Thinkers, Binghamton, N.Y., Global Academic Publishing, 2005, pp. 61-70 (originally 1992).
  37. McGinnis, J. (2006), “Making Abstraction Less Abstract: The Logical, Psychological, and Metaphysical Dimensions in Avicenna’s Theory of Abstraction,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 80, 169-83.
  38. Pellat, Charles, ‘Ankâ’ in Encyclopaedia of Islam, ed. by H.A.R. Gibb et alii, 2nd. ed., vol. 1 (Ledien: Brill, 1960), p. 509.
  39. Steel, C. (2002), “Avicenna and Aquinas on Evil,” in Avicenna and his Heritage, ed. J. Janssens & D. De Smet (Ancient and Medieval Philosophy, 28), Louvain, Leuven University Press, 171-96.
  40. Zimmermann, F. W. (1981), Al-Farabi’s Commentary and Short Treatise on Aristotle’s De intepretatione (The British Academy Classical and Medieval Logic Texts), London, Oxford University Press.