Número 26 - 2004
Articles

Common Sense in Saul Kripke as Method

Carlos López Zaragoza
Universidad Panamericana

Published 2013-11-28

How to Cite

Zaragoza, C. L. (2013). Common Sense in Saul Kripke as Method. Tópicos, Revista De Filosofía, 26(1), 67–98. https://doi.org/10.21555/top.v26i1.260

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

Altmetrics

Citas

Abstract

This paper intends to show that the main goals of Saul Kripke's theory of reference depend on the methodological use of common sense, understanding by common sense the natural way in which intelligence approaches reality and in which is reflected in natural or ordinary language. The key to shed light on  Kripke's ideas about common sense is to analyze the texts in which he deals with 'intuition'.

 

References

  1. Araos, J. (1999). La filosofía aristotélica del lenguaje. Pamplona: EUNSA.
  2. Burgess, J. (1998). Marcus, Kripke and names. En The New Theory of Reference. Kripke, ​Marcus, and Its Origins. P. W. Humphreys and J. H. Fetzer (ed.) (89-124) Dordrecht: ​Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  3. Conesa, F., Nubiola, J. (1999). Filosofía del lenguaje. Barcelona: Herder.
  4. Flamarique, L. (1991). Necesidad y conocimiento. Fundamentos de la teoría crítica de I. Kant. Pamplona: EUNSA.
  5. Frege, G. (1979). Escritos lógico-semánticos. Madrid: Tecnos.
  6. Kripke, S. (1969). Identity and Necessity. En Identity and Individuation. M. K. Munitz (ed.) ​New York: New York University Press.
  7. ____ (1975). Outline of a Theory of Truth. En Journal of Philosophy, 72: 690-716.
  8. ____ (1976). Is There a Problem about Substitutional Quantification? En Truth and ​Meaning: Essays in semantics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  9. ____ (1979). A Puzzle about Belief. En Meaning and Use. A. Margalit (ed.) (239-291) ​Boston: Reidel.
  10. ____ (1980). Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.
  11. ____ (1982). On Rules and Private Languages. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  12. Leibniz, G. W. (1863). Die Philosophiscen Schriften. Vol. 7. Berlín: Weidmann.
  13. Marcus, R. (1946). A Functional Calculus of First order Based on Strict Implication. En ​Journal of Symbolic Logic, 11.
  14. ____ (1961). Modalities and Intensional Languages. En Syntese, 13: 303-322.
  15. ____ (1963). Modalities and Intensional Languages. Dordrecht: Boston.
  16. ____ (1971). Essential Attribution. En Journal of Philosophy, 68: 187-202.
  17. Mill, J. S. (1973). Collected Works. Toronto: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
  18. Nubiola, J. (1984). El compromiso esencialista de la lógica modal. Pamplona: EUNSA.
  19. Pérez, M. (1991). Predicación esencial y predicación accidental en Aristóteles. Tesis ​doctoral. Pro Manuscrito. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra.
  20. Polo, L. (1987). Curso de teoría del conocimiento. Vol. 1. Pamplona: EUNSA.
  21. Powers, J. (1992). On Being Wrong: Krpike’s Casual Theory of Reference. En International ​Philosophical Quarterly, 22 (4): 459-479.
  22. Prior, A. (1976). Historia de la lógica. Madrid: Tecnos.
  23. Soames, S. (1998). Revisionism about Reference. En The New Theory of Reference. Kripke, ​Marcus, and Its Origins. P. W. Humphreys and J. H. Fetzer (ed.) (65-88). Dordrecht: ​Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  24. Torra, F. (1996). Necesidad y contingencia en la filosofía leibniciana. Roma: Pontificia ​Universidad de la Santa Cruz.
  25. Wittgenstein, L. (1961). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
  26. ____ (1988). Investigaciones Filosóficas. A. García y U. Moulines (trads.) Barcelona: Crítica.
  27. Zagal, H. (2000). L’attualità del metodo aristotelico. En L’attualità di Aristotele. Roma: ​Armando.